The Universe of Things ─ Steven Shaviro



I begin with a short story called “The Universe of Things,” by the British science
fiction writer Gwyneth Jones (2010). The story is about an encounter between a
human being and an alien. It is part of Jones’s “Aleutian” cycle: a series of novels
and stories set in a near-future Earth that is visited, colonized, and ultimately
abandoned by an alien humanoid race. The Aleutians (as these aliens are called)
have technologies that are superior to ours. Also, they are of indeterminate gender;
human beings tend to be discomfited by this. If anything, the Aleutians vaguely
seem to be more “feminine” than “masculine”; but human beings usually refer to
them with the pronoun “it.” For both of these reasons, the Aleutians’ presence on
our planet is traumatic and humiliating. It’s not that they do anything particularly
nasty or unpleasant; but their very existence somehow diminishes us. We find
ourselves in a position of abject dependency; even the most affluent white male
Westerners must now count themselves among the ranks of the colonized.
The Aleutians’ presence on Earth undermines our inveterate anthropocentrism.
“Man” is no longer the measure of all things. We can no longer think of ourselves
as being special, much less take ourselves as the pinnacle of creation. Modernity
is often seen as a long series of displacements and decenterings of the human; just
think of Copernicus, Darwin, and Freud, or for that matter of Deep Blue defeating
Garry Kasparov. Jones’s Aleutians mark the ne plus ultra of this tendency; their
effortless superiority leaves us blank and at a loss. And this is not just a matter
of First Contact, so frequently mythologized in science fiction narratives. Jones’s
aliens stay on the Earth for centuries. The fact of their existence never loses its
disturbing edge, even as it comes to be woven into the habits and assumptions of
everyday human life. In this way, the Aleutian cycle is a narrative about – among
other things – the adjustments forced upon us as we enter a posthuman era.
Within Gwyneth Jones’s overall Aleutian cycle, “The Universe of Things” fo-
1
cuses upon one of the most striking differences between the aliens and ourselves:
the fact that their technology, unlike ours, is intrinsically alive. The Aleutians’
tools are biological extrusions of themselves: “they had tools that crept, slithered,
flew, but they had made these things. . . They built things with bacteria. . . Bacteria
which were themselves traceable to the aliens’ own intestinal flora, infecting
everything.” In effect, the Aleutians literalize Marshall McLuhan’s thesis that
all media are prosthetic extensions of ourselves. The Aleutians exteriorize themselves
in every aspect of their environment. Their networks extend far beyond
their own bodies and immediate surroundings. They are even able to share feelings
and memories, as these are chemcially encoded in the slime that they exude,
and exchange with one another. In consequence, “the aliens could not experience
being a-part. There were no parts in their continuum: no spaces, no dividing
edges.” They are alive in the midst of an entirely “living world.”
The living world of the Aleutians stands in sharp and bitter contrast to the way
that we remain trapped by our sad Cartesian legacy. We tend to dread our own
mechanistic technologies, even as we use them more and more. We cannot escape
the pervasive sense, endemic toWestern culture, that we are alone in our aliveness,
trapped in a world of dead, or merely passive, matter. Our own machines, Jones
writes, “promised, but they could not perform. They remained things, and people
remained lonely.” It seems to some of the people in Jones’s stories that, in contrast
to this situation, “the aliens had the solution to human isolation: a talking world,
a world with eyes; the companionship that God dreams of.”
“The Universe of Things” tells the story of a human auto mechanic whom an alien
hires to fix its car. The mechanic, like most human beings, both regards the aliens
with awe, and at the same time feels a bit afraid of them. He is honored and
humbled, but also made extremely anxious, when the alien entrusts the repair of
its vehicle to him. He doesn’t know why he has been singled out for this job;
nor does he know why the alien uses an inferior (and ecologically harmful) earth
technology in the first place, instead of sticking with the Aleutians’ own mode of
living transport. In any case, the mechanic focuses all of his confused feelings
upon the car. Wanting to maintain “the mystique of craftsmanship,” the one sort
of human pride that remains to him, he turns off all the machines that usually do
the repair work in his shop, and resolves to fix the alien’s car by hand.
In the course of a long evening, as he works on the car, the mechanic has an
epiphany – or a hallucination. He experiences, for a moment, what the aliens’
“living world” is actually like: his own tools seem to come alive. The experience
2
is disconcerting, to say the least. “He stared at the spanner in his hand until the
rod of metal lost its shine. Skin crept over it, the adjustable socket became a cup
of muscle, pursed like an anus, wet lips drawn back by a twist on the tumescent
rod.” The living world is obscene and pornographic. Existence is suffocating
and unbearable. Everything is suffused by “living slime. . . full of self, of human
substance,” but somehow rendered other. This is what happens when you have
“succeeded in entering the alien mind, seen the world through alien eyes. How
could you expect such an experience to be pleasant?” The mechanic is terrified
and nauseated. All he wants is to return to the loneliness and security of the
customary human world: a world in which objects remain at a proper distance
from us, because they are “dead, and safe.”
“The Universe of Things” encourages us to think about the liveliness of objects,
and about the ways that they are related to us. The story suggests that, even
when we have shaped things into tools, and thereby constrained them to serve
our own purposes, they still have independent lives of their own. That is to say,
tools (like things in general) are what Bruno Latour calls actants – just as much
as we ourselves are (Latour 1988, 159). Things have their own powers, their own
innate tendencies. When we make use of things, employing them as tools, we are
really allying ourselves with them (Harman 2009, 19). But alliance also means
dependency; we discover that we cannot do anything without our tools’ help. The
story therefore posits something like what Jane Bennett calls vital materialism:
the recognition that “vitality is shared by all things,” and not limited to ourselves
alone (Bennett 2010, 89).
But even as the story intimates this, it also dramatizes our fear of the liveliness
of things. In the mechanic’s experience, wonder turns into dread. The sense that
everything is filled with “human substance” flips over into the paranoid vision of a
menacing alien vitality. The magic of a fully animate world becomes a nightmare
of Cthulhu. We are threatened by the vibrancy of matter. We need to escape
the excessive proximity of things. We cannot bear the thought of their having an
autonomous life, even if this life is ultimately attributable to us. We are desperate
to reassure ourselves that, in spite of everything, objects are, after all, passive and
inert.
It is important that Jones’s story is not about “things” in general; rather, it is specifically
about tools. For tools are probably the objects in relation to which we most
fully confront the paradoxes of nonhuman actants, of vital matter, and of object
independence. Tools are extensions of ourselves, things that we have shaped ex-
3
plicitly in order to serve our own needs. They are supposed to be subordinate to
our will. And indeed, most of the time, we don’t even think about our tools; they
are simply there. As Heidegger puts it – at least in the most common interpretation
of his work – tools are ready-to-hand, available to us. And yet, this very
availability of our tools gives them a strange autonomy and vitality. We find that
we cannot just use them. We must learn to work with them, rather than against
them. We have to accomodate their nature, and their needs, as well as our own.
My mention of Heidegger’s readiness-to-hand (Zuhandenheit) is not fortuitous.
For I think that “The Universe of Things” can well be read as an allegory of
what Graham Harman, expanding Heidegger’s concept, calls tool-being (Harman
2002). Harman explicitly criticizes the common reading of readiness-to-hand in
pragmatic terms – which is the way I used the concept a moment ago. According
to Harman, readiness-to-hand does not mean the practical handling of things, as
opposed to their explicit theorization (125-126). Rather, the category of the readyto-
hand has a much broader reach. It does not consist “solely of human devices. . .
We can speak of the readiness-to-hand even of dead moths and of tremors on a
distant sun. As ‘useless’ as these things may be, they still exert their reality within
the total system of entities” (152). Things are active and interactive far beyond
any measure of their presence to us. Tool-being does not apply just to the human
use of things; it is a far more fundamental ontological category. Gwyneth Jones’s
story begins with the familiar sense of tools as objects of use, but it culminates in
the mechanic’s discovery that the “universe of things” has a deeper reality.
The crucial point about tool-being, in Harman’s analysis, is that it involves a radical
withdrawal from simple presence, and therefore from any possibility of theorization.
Throughout Heidegger’s work, Harman says, “the single error to be
guarded against lies in the ingrained habit of regarding beings as present-at-hand,
as representable in terms of delineable properties rather than acknowledged in the
actus of being what they are” (Harman 2002, 27). Opposing this reduction, Heidegger
always insists that “what exists outside of human contexts does not have
the mode of being of presence-at-hand” (126). To reduce a thing to its presenceat-
hand – which is to say to the sum of its delineable properties – is precisely to
regard that thing as only the correlate of a consciousness perceiving it (Meillassoux
2008). But a thing is always more than its qualities; it always exists and acts
independently of, and in excess over, the particular ways that we grasp and comprehend
it. This is why Harman credits Heidegger with providing us a way out
from correlationism, and towards an object-oriented ontology.
4
Harman argues that all entities are tool-beings; none of them may be simply reduced
to presence-at-hand, or to a simple list of properties. But tool-being itself
is double. It has “two distinct senses. It is the performance of a withering subterranean
force, but a force that also acts to summon up some explicitly encountered
reality” (Harman 2002, 26). On the one hand, Harman says, “tool-beings. . . recede
into the work of an unnoticed background. . . Dissolved into a general equipmental
effect, entities vanish into a unique system of reference, losing their singularity”
(44-45). This is what allows us to take our tools for granted; we don’t even notice
them as objects, most of the time. We rely on their “equipmental effect,” forgetting
that this efficacy is itself the result of a vast network of alliances, mediations,
and relays. Such is the initial, complacent assumption of the mechanic in “The
Universe of Things.”
But at the same time, and on the other hand, tool-being also involves a countermovement,
a reversal. This is epitomized by Heidegger in the form of the “broken
tool.” When a tool, or a thing, fails to function as expected, then the excess of its
being is suddenly revealed to us. As Harman wonderfully describes it, radicalizing
Heidegger, there is “an uprising of distinct elements. . . a surge of minerals and
battle flags and tropical cats into the field of life, where each object bears a certain
demeanor and seduces us in a specific way, bombarding us with its energies like a
miniature neutron star” (Harman 2002, 47). When this happens, the tool is morethan-
present; it stands forth too actively and aggressively for me to posit it as
present-at-hand. That is to say, the tool, or the thing, becomes alive – as the
mechanic suddenly experiences in the story. And this uprising, or unveiling, is
the very basis of object-oriented ontology, which Harman describes as an effort
“to do justice to the distinctive force of these specific objects, to the eruption of
personalities from the empire of being” (47).
I take this analysis, from the beginning of Harman’s first book, Tool-Being, as fundamental
– even though Harman himself rejects it. For, although Harman starts
out with Heidegger’s understanding of the tool and the broken tool, he quickly
moves onto different ground. The first part of Tool-Being describes a double
movement: a retreat into the universal referentiality of equipment, or into “an
oppressive totality withdrawn from view and devoid of particular beings” (Harman
2002, 47), followed by the eruption of absolute singularities, each object’s
emergence “defining a fateful tear in the contexture of meaning, the birth of an individual
power to be reckoned with” (47). But in the course of the book, Harman
collapses this dichotomy. He argues, instead, that the object’s withdrawal from
5
presence is a retreat from referentiality as well. This means that “the tool-being of
a thing exists in vacuum-sealed isolation, exceeding any of the relations that might
touch it” (287). Instead of swinging between an excess of referentiality on the one
hand, and an excess of singularity on the other, each object both disappears into,
and emerges out of, its own inaccessible vacuum. Harman carefully notes that,
as a result of this reformulation, “both Heidegger and Whitehead become direct
opponents of my theory” (228).
I have taken Whitehead’s side (and somewhat to my surprise, Heidegger’s as
well!) against Harman in an article published (along with his rebuttal) in The Speculative
Turn; I will not pursue that polemic here. Instead, I will simply continue
to explore the further, positive implications of the double movement that Harman
finds in Heidegger’s account of tools and broken tools. Indeed, this doubleness is
crucial to Gwyneth Jones’s story. “The Universe of Things” turns precisely upon
the way that objects are irreducible to simple presence. And it also suggests that
this excess has two complementary aspects. The “universe of things” is, on the
one hand, altogether systematic and auto-referential; as a ubiquitous medium, or
extension of ourselves, it stretches well beyond whatever is immediately apparent
or present. It turns upon the irony that, when “human substance” is everywhere,
that substance gets stretched and scattered beyond recognition. This is the same
process that Marshall McLuhan is getting at, when he describes media as “the extensions
of man” (McLuhan 1994). For media spread themselves out everywhere.
Once we project them, they escape from our control and redound back upon us,
drawing us into new relations. “All media work us over completely. . . they leave
no part of us untouched, unaffected, unaltered” (McLuhan and Fiore 1967, 26).
But on the other hand, the “universe of things” also shows itself in the obscene
eruption of individual objects, in all their liveliness and singularity. When “all
the tools. . . leap into action,” the mechanic is assailed by “the ghostly feel of flesh
in the machines.” In each of these machines, he finds a “drop of self,” a living
will. His dread at this prospect exemplifies McLuhan’s observation that the emergence
of new media is “too violent and superstimulated a social experience for
the central nervous system to endure” (McLuhan 1994, 43). Such a heightening
of contact with the universe of things is traumatic. The auto mechanic is reduced
to nausea and panic. He has experienced the worst of both sides of tool-being. He
is stifled by the “oppressive totality” into which his tools have withdrawn for their
“equipmental effect.” But equally, he feels menaced by the “uprising” of his tools
as “distinct elements,” flaunting their autonomy and demanding his attention.
6
The double movement of tool-being – as both retreat and eruption – points to two
alternative, but co-existing, ways in which things are forever escaping our grasp.
What retreat and eruption have in common is that they are alike irreducible to any
correlation of subject and object, or of human perceiver and world perceived. They
are both modes of escape from presence, and from a human-centered context. If
I cannot control and instrumentalize a thing, this is both because it draws me
into extended referential networks whose full ramifications I cannot trace, and
because its singularity, bursting forth, stuns me in excess of anything that I can
posit about it. Retreat and eruption are both movements by means of which things
demonstrate that there is more to them than we can gather of them. A thing can
never be fully defined by any list, no matter how extended, of it characteristics and
qualities. For beyond all these, it has its own autonomous power. As Jane Bennett
puts it, “the capacity of these bodies [i]s not restricted to a passive ‘intractability,’
but also include[s] the ability to make things happen, to produce effects. . . All
bodies become more than mere objects, as the thing-powers of resistance and
protean agency are brought into sharper relief” (Bennett 2010, 5, 13).
Tool-being is therefore irreducible to use – in the same way, and for the same
reasons, that it is irreducible to presence. And this has a further, perhaps surprising,
consequence. When objects encounter one another, the basic mode of their
relation is neither theoretical nor practical, and neither epistemological nor ethical.
Rather, before either of these, every relation among objects is an aesthetic
one. As Harman puts it, “aesthetics becomes first philosophy” (Harman 2007b,
205). For aesthetics is about the singularity and supplementarity of things. That
is to say, it has to do with things insofar as they cannot be cognized, or subordinated
to concepts; and also insofar as they cannot be utilized, or normatively
regulated, or defined according to rules. No matter how deeply I comprehend a
thing, and no matter how pragmatically or instrumentally I make use of it, there
is still something of it that escapes my categorizations. Even when I obliterate a
thing, or consume it utterly, there is still something of it that I have not managed
to incorporate, some force to it that I have not been able to subsume. Aesthetics
involves feeling an object for its own sake, beyond those aspects of it that can
be understood or used. The thing withdraws into its network, luring me into the
shadows; and it bursts forth in a splendour that dazzles and blinds me. In these
cases, the understanding is frustrated, and the will reaches the limits of its power.
It is only aesthetically, beyond understanding and will, that I can appreciate the
actus of the thing being what it is, in what Harman calls “the sheer sincerity of
existence” (Harman 2005, 135).
7
The dazzlement of things bursting forth is what Harman calls allure: the sense of
an object’s existence apart from, and over and above, its own qualities (Harman
2005, 142-144). Allure has to do with the showing-forth of that which is, strictly
speaking, inaccessible; it “invites us toward another level of reality” (179). In
the event of allure, I encounter the very being of a thing, beyond all definition or
correlation. I am forced to acknowledge its integrity, entirely apart from me. Such
an encounter alters the parameters of the world, tearing apart “the contexture of
meaning,” and rupturing every consensus. It introduces what Whitehead would
call a novelty: a new entity, something that does not belong to the already-said,
and does not sit well within any previously-agreed-upon horizon. For Harman,
allure is therefore “the engine of change within the world” (179).
But there is also a kind of aesthetic event that has to do with the retreat of things
beyond our grasp, and “into the work of an unnoticed background.” This is what
we might call metamorphosis, in contrast to allure. Metamorphosis is a kind of
wayward attraction, a movement of withdrawal and substitution, a continual play
of becoming. In metamorphosis, it is not the thing itself that attracts me, over and
above its qualities; it is rather the very unsteadiness of the thing that draws me
onward, as it ripples and shifts in a kind of protean wavering. All of the thing’s
attributes become unstable, as it slips and slides beneath them, retreating into the
background, relating and referring beyond my capacity to follow. Metamorphosis
thus reflects the way that, as Whitehead puts it, “every actual entity is present in
every other actual entity” (Whitehead 1929/1978, 50). In the movement of allure,
the web of meaning is ruptured, as the thing emerges violently from its context;
but in the movement of metamorphosis, the web of meaning is multiplied and
extended, echoed and distorted, propagated to infinity, as the thing loses itself in
the network of its own ramifying traces. The auto mechanic in “The Universe of
Things” is overwhelmed by both of these movements at once.
Both allure and metamorphosis are instances of what Whitehead calls “lures for
feeling” (1929/1978, 25, 184, and passim). This is one of Whitehead’s most peculiar
expressions, but I think that it well describes the basis of aesthetic attraction
(and repulsion). A lure is anything that, in some way, works to capture my attention.
It may entice me, or incite me, or seduce me, or tempt me, or compel me,
or even bludgeon and bully me. But in any case, it addresses me from beyond.
The lure is what Whitehead calls a proposition. Whitehead defines propositions
(of which logical propositions are only a special case) as “tales that perhaps might
be told about particular actualities” (256). In other words, a proposition proposes
8
some sort of potentiality to me; it holds forth the prospect of a difference. And
this potentiality or difference is always anchored in some “particular actuality,” in
an actual thing or a group of things.
Whitehead thus agrees with Husserl, Heidegger, and Harman that I do not encounter
things just as bare packets of sensa, or as present-at-hand bundles of qualities.
Rather, we should say that things proposition me, or that they offer me a
certain “promise of happiness” (to cite Stendhal’s famous description of beauty).
The qualities of a thing – or more precisely, what Whitehead calls the “eternal
objects” that are incarnated in it – are only the bait that the thing holds out to
me, in order to draw me toward it. It may be that a particular thing dazzles me
when it rises up from the depths; or it may be that it intrigues and bemuses me, by
withdrawing into endless labyrinths. But in either case, a lure has been “proposed
for feeling, and when admitted into feeling it constitutes what is felt” (Whitehead
1929/1978, 187). When I respond to a lure – and even if I respond to it negatively,
by rejecting it – I am led to envision a possibility, or to “entertain a proposition”
(188), and thereby to feel something that I would not have felt otherwise.
I think that the question of feeling is central here. Entities generally do not “know”
one another; Harman is entirely right to say that a thing’s reality is “irreducible
to what is perceived of it” (Harman 2005, 187), and that, when objects meet, they
“fail to exhaust one another’s reality” (188). But this cognitive and pragmatic failure
is not the end of the story. For Whitehead suggests that entities interact by
“feeling” one another, even in the absence of knowledge and power. Things encounter
one another aesthetically, and not just cognitively or practically. I always
feel more of a thing than I actually know of it; and I feel it otherwise than I know
it. To the extent that I do know an object, I am able to put it to use, to enumerate
its qualities, to break it down into its constituent parts, and to trace the causes that
have determined it. But feeling an object involves something else as well. I feel
a thing when it affects me, or changes me. And what thus affects me is not just
certain qualities of the thing, but its total and irreducible existence.
In Whitehead’s terms, our always-incomplete knowledge of things comes in the
form of the “well-marked familiar sensa” of “presentational immediacy” (Whitehead
1929/1978, 176). These are the ideas and impressions of the empiricists, the
denumerable properties of an object. Presentational immediacy is the realm of
Descartes’ “clear and distinct” ideas; it is roughly equivalent to what Heidegger
disparages as mere presence-at-hand. But things already affect one another prior
to any such presentation of explicit qualities, in the mode of what Whitehead
9
calls “causal efficacy.” In this mode, “the inflow into ourselves of feelings from
enveloping nature overwhelms us; in the dim consciousness of half-sleep, the presentations
of sense fade away, and we are left with the vague feeling of influences
from vague things around us” (176).
It is only in the realm of presentational immediacy, with its inevitable limitations
and failures, that we are faced with Harman’s paradoxes of “sensual objects”
that must be distinguished from real ones (Harman 2007b, 76-81), and of occasionalism
or vicarious causation (Harman 2005, 169-234). In the realm of causal
efficacy, we have rather to do with a sort of total contact, a promiscuous interchange
among objects. These encounters cannot entirely be cognized; they are
never clear and distinct, but always leave us “prey to vague feelings of influence”
(Whitehead 1929/1978, 176). But the conceptual vagueness of these experiences
does not lessen their power; quite the contrary. A feeling always involves some
alteration of the one who feels. For Whitehead, experience is being; what an entity
feels is what that entity is. This means that, as the result of “entertaining”
a lure, I have somehow been transformed – whether grandly or minutely. I have
selected one definite outcome from among “the penumbral welter of alternatives”
(187). As a result, I have become – however slightly or massively – a different
entity from the one that I was before this happened. I am no longer the same as I
might have been, had I not been moved by this particular “flash of novelty” (184).
There is more than a hint of Romanticism in Whitehead’s notion of causal efficacy,
just as there is in Heidegger’s related notion of a world of equipment, forming
“a single gigantic system of references” (Harman 2007a, 62). The withdrawal
of things into an ever-ramifying network of traces has much in common with
the early-nineteenth-century Romantic idea of nature – although today we should
rather associate it with the mediasphere, or with the global financial network; or
else with the World Wide Web, especially as it develops into what Bruce Sterling
has felicitously called the “Internet of Things” (Sterling 2005, 92-94). Whitehead
makes this link to Romanticism explicit, when he points up the way that “the irresistible
causal efficacy of nature presses itself upon us; in the vagueness of the
low hum of insects in an August woodland, the inflow into ourselves of feelings
from enveloping nature overwhelms us” (Whitehead 1929/1978, 176). This vague
sense of total envelopment is not peculiar to human beings; it extends throughout
the natural world, and is felt by animals and plants (176). Indeed, Whitehead
claims that even inorganic entities experience something like an “influx of feeling,”
at least in the form of flows of energy, because “all fundamental physical
10
qualities are vector and not scalar” (177).
In Science and the Modern World (1925/1967), Whitehead considers the Romantic
idea of nature at greater length. He does this in a chapter (“The Romantic
Reaction,” 75-94) that includes a discussion of several British Romantic works.
(This is one of the very rare cases in which Whitehead cites literary texts, instead
of philosophical ones). One of the works that Whitehead examines is Percy
Bysshe Shelley’s poem “Mont Blanc” – the very text that provided Gwyneth Jones
with the title for her short story. Shelley’s poem begins with a description of how
The everlasting universe of things
Flows through the mind,
and it continues with an evocation of
My own, my human mind, which passively
Now renders and receives fast influencings,
Holding an unremitting interchange
With the clear universe of things around.
Whitehead remarks that, in spite of this poem’s “explicit reference to some form
of idealism,” nonetheless Shelley “is here an emphatic witness to a prehensive
unification as constituting the very being of nature” (86). I think that this comment
is worth unpacking. For idealism, we might today read correlationism; for the
poem explicitly explores correspondences between the human mind as perceiving
subject, and the outside world as that which is perceived. Whitehead leaves it
an open question as to whether Shelley’s idealism is “Kantian or Berkeleyan or
Platonic” (86); subsequent scholarship suggests that Shelley rather advocated a
kind of empiricism-turned-sceptical-idealism, derived from William Drummond,
a now largely forgotten disciple of Hume (Pulos 1954). But in any case, the poem
displays an overwhelming concern with subject/object dualism.
However, Whitehead suggests that the rhetoric of “Mont Blanc” undermines its
apparent empiricism and idealism. For the poem states that it is actually “things”
themselves – rather than their representations in the form of ideas or impressions
– that flow through the mind. Shelley’s insistence upon a universe of actually
existing things goes against the subjectivism and sensationalism of the rest of the
poem, and of British empiricism more generally. (Whitehead defines subjectivism
11
as the notion “that the datum in the act of experience can be adequately analysed
purely in terms of universals,” and sensationalism as the notion “that the primary
activity in the act of experience is the bare subjective entertainment of the datum,
devoid of any subjective form of reception” – 1929/1978, 157). To the extent
that the poem envisions a “universe of things,” it suggests that we perceive and
respond to objects themselves: to the actus of their being what they are. We do not
just analyze them in terms of universals, by adding up and associating atomistic
“ideas.” My sense that “this stone is grey,” for instance, is not a primary datum
of experience, but only “a derivative abstraction” (160). Implicitly for Shelley, as
explicitly for Whitehead, all our mental impressions refer and belong to alreadyexisting
things; “the operations of the mind originate from ideas ‘determined’
to particular existents” (138). We do not just passively receive a series of bare,
isolated sensa; rather, we actually do encounter Mont Blanc, with its surrounding
glaciers and woods and waterfalls. The Romantic experience of nature points us
towards Whitehead’s claim “that there are many actual existents, and that in some
sense one actual existent repeats itself in another actual existent” (139).
“Mont Blanc” subverts its own explicit thematics in other ways as well. On one
level, the poem is clearly sensationalist and correlationist; it posits a subject/object
binary, with “my own, my human mind” passively registering impressions from
“the clear universe of things around.” But at the same time, the poem also suggests
that not just “my human mind,” but all entities without exception, engage in
the “unremitting interchange” of rendering and receiving “fast influencings.” This
is what leads Whitehead to say that nature, for Shelley, is “in its essence a nature
of organisms” (Whitehead 1925/1967, 85), each of them separately perceiving,
interacting with, and integrating its feelings of all the rest. More generally,
Whitehead insists that “both Shelley and Wordsworth emphatically bear witness
that nature cannot be divorced from its aesthetic values; and that these values arise
from the cumulation, in some sense, of the brooding presence of the whole onto
its various parts” (86-88). These “aesthetic values” involve both allure and metamorphosis.
Mont Blanc allures us, as it “gleams on high,” manifesting a Power
that “dwells apart in its tranquility,/ Remote, serene, and inaccessible.” But this
solitary, vacuum-sealed Power is also an actor in a vast web of interconnections:
a force of metamorphosis that “rolls its perpetual stream” through all things, exceeding
“the limits of the dead and living world,” and even potentially working
“to repeal/ Large codes of fraud and woe.” The separation of entities, and their
“cumulation” or interpenetration, are two sides of the same coin; they are alike
irreducible to subjectivism, sensationalism, and simple presence.
12
The interpenetration and “cumulation” of things in nature explains why, as Whitehead
concedes, we often experience causal efficacy in the form of “vague terrors”
(Whitehead 1929/1978, 176). We are made uneasy when we feel “the haunting
presences of nature” (Whitehead 1925/1967, 83), without quite knowing what
they are. Things are just too suffocatingly close for us to be able to regard them
as manipulable, or understandable, or present-at-hand. The intimacy of things is
always discomfiting and uncanny; it can easily seem obscene and directly menacing,
as it does to Gwyneth Jones’s mechanic. Marshall McLuhan, in his account
of oral, networked cultures, similarly suggests that “terror is the normal state” of
a situation in which “everything affects everything all the time” (1962, 32). For
Whitehead, things both differentiate themselves absolutely from one another, and
refer themselves incessantly to one another. The terror of interconnection is a
kind of inverse, like a photographic negative, of the “satisfaction” with which an
entity uniquely constitutes itself “into a completely determinate matter of fact”
(Whitehead 1929/1978, 212).
Whitehead thus insists upon both the integrity of “particular existents,” and “the
brooding presence of the whole” of nature. This double assertion corresponds to
the way that all entities perform a double movement of allure and metamorphosis,
of bursting forth and slipping away, of displaying their absolute singularity and
retreating into a maze of references and transformations. Each entity is “fully
determinate” in and of itself (Whitehead 1929/1978, 26); and yet they all belong to
a common world (Whitehead 1925/1967, 88-89). “The actual elements perceived
by our senses are in themselves the elements of a common world,” Whitehead
says; “this world is a complex of things, including indeed our acts of cognition,
but transcending them” (88). We find ourselves always already “within a world
of colours, sounds, and other sense-objects, related in space and time to enduring
objects such as stones, trees, and human bodies. We seem to be ourselves elements
of this world in the same sense as are the other things which we perceive” (89).
Things remain distinct from one another; but they are all “elements. . . in the same
sense” of the same common world. This insistence is what links Whitehead to
Deleuze, who also maintains that “being is said in a single and same sense” of all
entities, even as these entities retain their difference from one another (Deleuze
1994, 42). The double movement of withdrawal and belonging is what makes
possible a “democracy of objects” (as Levi Bryant beautifully calls it). Or, as
Whitehead puts it in Process and Reality, in a phrase that both refers back to
and expands upon William James, “we find ourselves in a buzzing world, amid a
democracy of fellow creatures” (Whitehead 1929/1978, 50).
13
I conclude with three brief points about this democracy of fellow creatures, this
universe of things. The first point has to do with anthropomorphism, the second
with vitalism, and the third with panpsychism. In the first place, throughout
this discussion I have freely used the first person, addressed issues of perception,
knowledge, and feeling, and argued for the primacy of aesthetics. Does this
not mean that I assume a human model after all, despite my rejection of anthropocentrism
and correlationism? The answer is that, for Whitehead, as for objectoriented
ontology, perception, feeling, and aesthetics are universal structures, not
specifically human ones. As Harman nicely puts it: “for Whitehead. . . humans
have no privilege at all; we can speak in the same way of the relation between
humans and what they see and that between hailstones and tar” (Harman 2009,
124). This also means that aesthetics as a mode of contact between beings “belongs
to ontology as a whole, not to the special metaphysics of animal perception”
(Harman 2007b, 205). If all entities inhere in the world “in the same sense,” then
we must describe this inherence in the same way for all of them.
But if I am to conceive a hailstone in the same way that I do a human subject,
then my only alternatives are eliminativism and anthropomorphism. I can always
follow the Churchlands, dismissing all accounts of human experience as misleading
“folk psychology,” and adopting the same reductive physicalist language to
describe human behavior as scientists use to describe the phase changes of water.
But if, together with Whitehead, I refuse to “indulge in brilliant feats of explaining
away” (Whitehead 1929/1978, 17), then I must accept that the categories I use
to describe myself are also valid for the hailstone. It has its own point of view,
just as I do; and that it somehow feels the tar with which it comes into contact,
much as I do. As I have already noted, Whitehead “attributes ‘feeling’ throughout
the actual world” (177) – though he doesn’t claim that a hailstone’s feelings are
conscious in the way that a human being’s are. The point is that a certain cautious
anthropomorphism is necessary, in order to avoid anthropocentrism. I attribute
feelings to hailstones, precisely in order to get away from the pernicious dualism
that would insist that human beings alone (or at most, human beings together with
some animals) have feelings, while everything else does not. As Jane Bennett puts
it, “maybe it is worth running the risks associated with anthropomorphism (superstition,
the divinization of nature, romanticism) because it, oddly enough, works
against anthropocentrism: a chord is struck between person and thing, and I am
no longer above or outside a nonhuman ‘environment.’ Too often the philosophical
rejection of anthropomorphism is bound up with a hubristic demand that only
humans and God can bear any traces of creative agency” (Bennett 2010, 120).
14
In the second place, if all entities have feelings and exert agency, this means that
they are all – at least to a certain extent – vital, active and creative. This cuts
against some of our most fundamental prejudices. Karen Barad observes that “the
inanimate-animate distinction is perhaps one of the most persistent dualisms in
Western philosophy and its critiques; even some of the most hard-hitting critiques
of the nature-culture dichotomy leave the animate-inanimate distinction in place.
It takes a radical rethinking of agency to appreciate how lively even ‘dead matter’
can be” (Barad 2007, 419). Getting rid of the living/nonliving distinction means
that – as Jane Bennett puts it – we can accept “neither vitalism nor mechanism”
(Bennett 2010, 62-81). Nineteenth-century vitalism, for instance, insisted upon “a
qualitative difference between entelechy-infused life and inorganic matter” (73).
The former was supposed to be active and goal-oriented, whereas the latter was
regarded as passive and mechanistic. But twentieth- and twenty-first-century science
makes this sort of distinction untenable. On the one hand, biochemistry since
the discovery of the structure of DNA has shown that life activities are continuous
with other physical and chemical processes; on the other hand, complexity
theory and systems theory (not to mention quantum mechanics) have shown that
even inorganic physical processes cannot be accurately conceived in traditionally
mechanistic terms. Modern science discredits traditional vitalism, but it doesn’t
leave traditional mechanistic materialism in a much better position.
Contemporary philosophers of science have, of course, constructed reductionist
theories that are no longer “mechanistic” in the old sense (e.g. Ladyman and Ross
2009). However, if we are to accept the ontological dignity of things, and do not
reduce them to being just the illusory effects of quantum fields, then I think that
we need to accept some sort of non-dualistic neo-vitalism, or what Jane Bennett
calls vital materialism: the idea that “every thing is entelechial, life-ly, vitalistic”
(Bennett 2010, 89). Whitehead similarly suggests that “there is no absolute gap
between ‘living’ and ‘non-living’ societies” (Whitehead 1929/1978, 102); moreover,
“we do not know of any living society devoid of its subservient apparatus of
inorganic societies” (103). “Life” is therefore a matter of degree, of a more and
a less; it can only be identified relatively and situationally. There are many intermediate
cases between life and nonlife: think of viruses, or of computer-based
“artificial life.” Even the simplest physical processes are more lively than we often
realize; and even the most unambiguously living processes are always embedded
within, and inextricably entangled with, comparatively nonliving ones. Vitality is
unevenly distributed, but it is at work everywhere. This is why the “democracy of
objects” is also a “democracy of fellow creatures.”
15
In the third place, and most controversially, I think that vital materialism and
object-oriented ontology both entail some sort of panexperientialism or panpsychism.
This is obviously not a step to be taken lightly; it can easily get one branded
as a crackpot. Most metaphysicians today, analytic or continental, science-oriented
or not, tend to reject panpsychism out of hand. Indeed, in my own recent book on
Whitehead, I was overly quick to deny the panpsychist implications of his thought
(Shaviro 2009, 28). I now think that my denial was wrong. For one thing, as David
Skrbina has argued at great and persuasive length, panpsychism has a long history
in, and is deeply embedded within, Western thought (Skrbina 2005). For another,
panpsychism has recently come to be entertained by thinkers of various persuasions,
including analytic philosophers like Galen Strawson (2006) and to some
extent David Chalmers (1997).
In the terms that I have set forth here, aesthetic experience is always asymmetrical;
it needs to posed in terms of a subject, as well as an object. A world of objects
is really a world of experiencings; as Whitehead insists, “apart from the experience
of subjects there is nothing, nothing, nothing, bare nothingness” (Whitehead
1929/1978, 167). For Whitehead, “each actuality is essentially bipolar, physical
and mental” (108); every actual entity has a “mental pole,” at least incipiently.
If we are to reject both the correlationist view that “the subject does not belong
to the world: rather, it is a limit of the world” (Wittgenstein 2001, 5.632), and
the eliminativist view that the subject is literally “no one” (Metzinger 2004), then
we must discover an immanent sense of subjectivity, or at least of some mode
of ‘having-experience.’ And if we accept Whitehead’s ontological principle, that
“there is nothing that floats into the world from nowhere” (Whitehead 1929/1978,
244), or Strawson’s argument against radical emergence (Strawson 2006, 12-21),
then we must at least be open to the prospect that ‘having-experience’ is already
intrinsic to all existing actual entities. I will not argue this proposition any further
here, but I wish to leave it as a lure for thought, a prospective consequence of the
fact that we find ourselves in a universe of things.
16
References
Barad, Karen (2007). Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the
Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Durham: Duke University Press.
Bennett, Jane (2010). Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things. Durham:
Duke University Press.
Chalmers, David J. (1997). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental
Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles (1994). Difference and Repetition. Trans. Paul Patton. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Harman, Graham (2002). Tool-Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects.
Chicago and LaSalle: Open Court.
— (2005). Guerrilla Metaphysics: Phenomenology and the Carpentry of Things.
Chicago and LaSalle: Open Court.
— (2007a). Heidegger Explained: From Phenomenon to Thing. Chicago and
LaSalle: Open Court.
— (2007b). “On Vicarious Causation.” In: Collapse: Philosophical Research and
Development 2.
— (2009). Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics. Melbourne:
re.press.
Jones, Gwyneth (2010). The Universe of Things. Seattle: Aqueduct Press.
Ladyman, James and Don Ross (2009). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Latour, Bruno (1988). The Pasteurization of France. Trans. Alan Sheridan and
John Law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
McLuhan, Marshall (1962). The Gutenberg Galaxy: The Making of Typographic
Man. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
— (1994). Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man. Cambridge: MIT
Press.
McLuhan, Marshall and Quentin Fiore (1967). The Medium is the Massage. New
York: Bantam.
Meillassoux, Quentin (2008). After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency.
Trans. Ray Brassier. New York: Continuum.
Metzinger, Thomas (2004). Being No One: The Self-Model Theory of Subjectivity.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Pulos, C. E. (1954). The Deep Truth: A Study of Shelley’s Skepticism. Lincoln:
University of Nebraska Press.
17
Shaviro, Steven (2009). Without Criteria: Kant, Whitehead, Deleuze, and Aesthetics.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Skrbina, David (2005). Panpsychism in the West. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Sterling, Bruce (2005). Shaping Things. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Strawson, Galen (2006). “Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism.”
In: Consciousness and Its Place in Nature: Does Physicalism Entail
Panpsychism? Ed. by Anthony Freeman. Exeter: Imprint Academic, pp. 3–31.
Whitehead, Alfred North (1925/1967). Science and the Modern World. New York:
The Free Press.
— (1929/1978). Process and Reality. New York: The Free Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (2001). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans. D. F. Pears
and B. F. McGuinness. New York: Routledge.
18

No hay comentarios:

Publicar un comentario